Civil Disobedience, Punishment, and Injustice

This chapter examines the tension between the justification and the punishment of civil disobedience, and theorists’ common solutions to it, by focusing on two central questions: first, should the state punish civil disobedience? Second, should the civil disobedient accept punishment? It presents the theoretical lay of the land on each of these questions, with particular attention to American jurisprudence on civil disobedience. The third part takes a step back to ask anew, how should we think about civil disobedience? and uncovers some problematic assumptions behind the common theoretical approach to the “problem” of civil disobedience.
This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.
Access this chapter
Subscribe and save
Springer+ Basic
€32.70 /Month
- Get 10 units per month
- Download Article/Chapter or eBook
- 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
- Cancel anytime
Buy Now
Price includes VAT (France)
eBook EUR 149.79 Price includes VAT (France)
Softcover Book EUR 189.89 Price includes VAT (France)
Hardcover Book EUR 189.89 Price includes VAT (France)
Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout
Purchases are for personal use only
Similar content being viewed by others

Civil Disobedience
Chapter © 2015

Civil Disobedience
Chapter © 2016

Criminal Justice and the Liberal State
Chapter © 2023
Notes
Agents ought to act nonviolently and openly and present their civil disobedience as an appeal to the foundational principles of consent, freedom of association, and the right to dissent (see Smith 2010).
To say that the right against punishment is presumptive is to recognize that there may be weighty countervailing reasons to punish or penalize civil disobedience. However, Brownlee contends that even when judges are justified to punish civil disobedients, they ought to apologize to the latter for infringing upon their rights.
A Plowshares case illustrates the state’s rigid stance and what’s at stake when civil disobedients fail to satisfy some of the non-evasion requirements identified above. Four anti-nuclearPlowshares defendants who insisted on explaining why they had trespassed a Johns Hopkins University research facility were found in contempt and removed from the courtroom. Daniel Berrigan shouted from the audience, “Let them speak, judge” and later added, “This court is a disgrace.” The judge demanded an apology and Berrigan defiantly replied, “I will change my position when you allow people in this court… to explain their actions.” Vaughn responded by holding Berrigan in contempt and sentenced him to five years in prison. See Buckley (1992).
Brownlee (2012) draws a distinction between conscience and conviction, which explains her change of terminology. “Conscience,” in her view, consists of “a set of practical moral skills that stem from an inward knowledge of the working of our own mind and heart,” while “conviction” refers to serious and sincere, though possibly mistaken, belief in a moral norm (Brownlee 2012, p. 52).
A portion of these protesters was part of a black block that smashed some windows.
I could summon many references here, but Anderson (2016) fits particularly well.
I am grateful to Chris Bennett, Koshka Duff, Ben Ewing, Kimberly Ferzan, Thomas Fossen, Robert Jubb, David Lyons, Andrei Poama, William Smith, and Aart Van Gils for their valuable feedback on earlier drafts.
References
- Commonwealth v. Berrigan, 325 Pa. Superior Ct. 242 (1984). Google Scholar
- Driskill v. Parrish, 7 F. Cas. 1100 (C.C.D. Ohio 1845) (No. 4,089). Google Scholar
- Florida House Bill No. 1419 (2017). Google Scholar
- Georgia Senate Bill 339 (2017–2018). Google Scholar
- Missouri House Bill No. 1413 (2018). Google Scholar
- North Dakota House Bill No. 1293 (2017). Google Scholar
- Roe v. Wade, 410 U.S. 113 (1973). Google Scholar
- United States v. Berrigan, 283 F. Supp. 336 (D. Md. 1968). Google Scholar
- United States v. Cobb, 25 F. Cas. 481, 482 (D.C.N.D. N.Y. 1857) (No. 14,820). Google Scholar
- United States v. Cullen, 454 F.2d 386, 392 (7th Cir. 1971). Google Scholar
- United States v. Kroncke, 459 F.2d 697 (8th Cir. 1972). Google Scholar
- United States v. Montgomery, 772 F.2d 733 (11th Cir. 1985). Google Scholar
- United States v. Schoon, 939 F.2d 826 (9th Cir. 1991). Google Scholar
- Walker v. Birmingham, 388 U.S. 307 (1967). Google Scholar
- Anderson, Carol. 2016. White rage: The unspoken truth of our racial divide. New York: Bloomsbury. Google Scholar
- Arendt, Hannah. 1970. Reflections on civil disobedience. New Yorker, September 12, 70–105. Google Scholar
- Bedau, Hugo. 1961. On civil disobedience. Journal of Philosophy 58: 653–665. ArticleGoogle Scholar
- Bentham, Jeremy. 1907. An introduction to the principles of morals and legislation. Oxford: Clarendon Press. (Orig. pub. 1789). Google Scholar
- Bourdieu, Pierre. 1998. Acts of resistance: Against the tyranny of the market. New York: The New Press. Google Scholar
- Boxerman, Arlene D. 1990. The use of the necessity defense by abortion clinic protesters. Journal of Criminal Law and Criminology 81: 677–712. ArticleGoogle Scholar
- Brownlee, Kimberley. 2008. Penalizing public disobedience. Ethics 118: 711–716. ArticleGoogle Scholar
- Brownlee, Kimberley. 2012. Conscience and conviction: The case for civil disobedience. Oxford: Oxford University Press. BookGoogle Scholar
- Buckley, Stephen. 1992. Berrigan released while appealing contempt term. The Washington Post, March 28. Google Scholar
- Cohan, John Alan. 2007. Civil disobedience and the necessity defense. Pierce Law Review 6: 111–175. Google Scholar
- Cohen, Carl. 1966. Civil disobedience and the law. Rutgers Law Review 21: 1–17. Google Scholar
- Cohen, Carl. 1971. Civil disobedience: Conscience, tactics, and the law. New York: Columbia University Press. Google Scholar
- Del Pozo, Brandon. 2018. Recent civil disobedience in Burlington. Burlington Free Press. https://www.burlingtonfreepress.com/story/new s/local/vermont/2018/02/23/why-didnt-police-arrest-uvm-protesters-burlington-chief-explains/368156002/. Accessed 26 Feb 2019.
- Delmas, Candice. 2018. A duty to resist: When disobedience should be uncivil. New York: Oxford University Press. BookGoogle Scholar
- Dworkin, Ronald. 1968. On not prosecuting civil disobedience. New York Review of Books, June 6. Google Scholar
- Dworkin, Ronald. 1985. A matter of principle. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Google Scholar
- Feinberg, Joel. 1965. The expressive function of punishment. The Monist 49: 397–423. ArticleGoogle Scholar
- Fortas, Abe. 1968. Dangers to the rule of law. American Bar Association Journal 54 (10): 957–959. Google Scholar
- Fortas, Abe. 1969. Concerning dissent and civil disobedience. New York: The New American Library, Signet Books. Google Scholar
- Germanos, Andrea. 2018. Judge drops charges against 13 who argued pipeline civil disobedience action was “necessary” to save planet. Common Dreams. https://www.commondreams.org/news/2018/03/28/judge-drops-charges-against-13-who-argued-pipeline-civil-disobedience-action-was. Accessed 26 Feb 2019.
- Hall, Matthew R. 2007. Guilty but civilly disobedient: Reconciling civil disobedience and the rule of law. Cardozo Law Review 28: 2083–2132. Google Scholar
- Horder, Jeremy. 2004. Excusing crime. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Google Scholar
- King, Martin Luther, Jr. 2003. A testament of hope: The essential writings and speeches. Ed. James M. Washington. New York: HarperCollins. Google Scholar
- Lefkowitz, David. 2007. On a moral right to civil disobedience. Ethics 117: 202–233. ArticleGoogle Scholar
- Lippman, Matthew. 1991. Towards a recognition of the necessity defense for political protesters. Washington & Lee Law Review 68: 235–251. Google Scholar
- Lippman, Matthew. 1994. Liberating the law: The jurisprudence of civil disobedience and resistance. San Diego Justice Journal 2: 317–394. Google Scholar
- Lyons, David. 1998. Moral judgment, historical reality, and civil disobedience. Philosophy and Public Affairs 27: 31–49. ArticleGoogle Scholar
- Markovits, Daniel. 2005. Democratic disobedience. Yale Law Journal 114: 1897–1952. Google Scholar
- Minow, Martha. 1991. Breaking the law: Lawyers and clients in struggles for social changes. University of Pittsburgh Law Review 52: 723–752. Google Scholar
- Moore, Michael S. 1997. Placing blame: A theory of criminal law. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Google Scholar
- Moraro, Piero. 2012. A dilemma for the civil disobedient: Pleading “guilty” or “not guilty” in the courtroom? In The public in law: Representations of the political in legal discourse, ed. Claudio Michelon, Gregor Clunie, Christopher McCorkindale, and Haris Psarras, 99–111. Edinburgh/Glasgow: Ashgate. Google Scholar
- Perkin, Charlotte. 2018. Stansted 15: Activists who stopped deportation charter flight convicted of terror-related charges. Novara Media. https://novaramedia.com/2018/12/10/stansted-15-activists-who-stopped-deportation-charter-flight-convicted-of-terrorism-charge/. Accessed 26 Feb 2019.
- Pineda, Erin. 2015. Civil disobedience and punishment: (Mis)reading justification and strategy from SNCC to Snowden. History of the Present 5: 1–30. ArticleGoogle Scholar
- Plato. 2002. Five dialogues: Euthyphro, apology, Crito, Meno, Phaedo. Trans. G.M.A. Grube and revised by John M. Cooper. Indianapolis: Hackett Classics. Google Scholar
- Rawls, John. 1999. A theory of justice. Rev. ed. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. (Orig. pub. 1971). Google Scholar
- Raz, Joseph. 1979. The authority of law. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Google Scholar
- Reagan, Leslie J. 1996. When abortion was a crime. Berkeley: University of California Press. Google Scholar
- Robin, Celikates. 2014. Civil disobedience as practice of civic freedom. In On global citizenship James Tully in dialogue, ed. David Owen, 207–228. London: Bloomsbury Press. Google Scholar
- Sabl, Andrew. 2001. Looking forward to justice: Rawlsian civil disobedience and its non-Rawlsian lessons. The Journal of Political Philosophy 9: 307–330. ArticleGoogle Scholar
- Sandalow, Terrance. 1969. Review of Concerning dissent and civil disobedience, by a. Fortas. Michigan Law Review 67: 599–612. ArticleGoogle Scholar
- Sarat, Austin. 2014. Keeping civility in its place: Dissent, injustice, and the lessons of history. In Law, society, and community: Socio-legal essays in honour of Roger Cotterrell, ed. Richard Nobes and David Schiff, 293–308. Abingdon: Routledge. Google Scholar
- Scheuerman, William E. 2018. Civil disobedience. Cambridge, UK: Polity Press. Google Scholar
- Shelby, Tommie. 2016. Dark ghettos: Injustice, dissent, and reform. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. BookGoogle Scholar
- Smith, William. 2010. Reclaiming the revolutionary spirit: Arendt on civil disobedience. European Journal of Political Theory 9: 149–166. ArticleGoogle Scholar
- Smith, William. 2013. Civil disobedience and deliberative democracy. Cambridge, UK: Routledge. BookGoogle Scholar
- Smith, William, and Luis Cabrera. 2015. The morality of border crossing. Contemporary Political Theory 14: 90–99. ArticleGoogle Scholar
- Stanton, Elizabeth Cady. 1969. Elizabeth Cady Stanton: As revealed in her letters & diary. Vol. 2. Eds. Theodore Stanton and Harriet Stanton Blatch. New York: Arno. Google Scholar
- Thoreau, Henry D. 2002. In The essays of Henry D. Thoreau, ed. Lewis Hyde. New York: North Point Press. Google Scholar
- Turenne, Sophie. 2004. Judicial responses to civil disobedience: A comparative approach. Res Publica 10: 379–399. ArticleGoogle Scholar
- Weinstock, Daniel. 2016. How democratic is civil disobedience? Criminal Law and Philosophy 10: 707–720. ArticleGoogle Scholar
- Woozley, A.D. 1976. Civil disobedience and punishment. Ethics 86: 323–331. ArticleGoogle Scholar
- Zinn, Howard. 2002. Disobedience and democracy: Nine fallacies of law and order. Cambridge, MA: South End Press. (Orig. pub. 1968.). Google Scholar
Author information
Authors and Affiliations
- Northeastern University, Boston, MA, USA Candice Delmas
- Candice Delmas